On Alienation from Life: A Response to Wendell KisnerÕs ÔA Species-Based
Environmental Ethic in HegelÕs Logic of LifeÕ
Wendell KisnerÕs article is important. It breaks the near-universal
silence about what the possible relations might be between Hegel and
environmental ethics. This silence is surprising: environmentalism has raced to
the top of the political agenda in the US and the UK, as in other countries,
while Hegel scholarship continues to flourish. Yet most environmental
philosophers remain caught in an image of Hegel as someone who favors mind and
reason at natureÕs expense, and the prevailing trend in Hegel studies –
the trend to read HegelÕs Ôdialectic as the public-communal constitution and
recognition of rational norms, free of ontological claims, in a kind of
historicized KantianismÕ – has not helped to dispel that image.[1]
So KisnerÕs arguments mark a welcome departure
from this historicized-Kantian approach. For Kisner, Hegelian philosophy has
the scope to intervene constructively into debates in environmental ethics,
specifically to provide a welcome alternative to the orientation towards
Ôintrinsic valueÕ found in so much environmental ethics. If I understand Kisner
rightly, he thinks that the very notion of ÔvalueÕ assumes a fact/value gap such
that ÔvalueÕ can only ever be external to ÔfactsÕ about environments and
organisms. Since environmentalist arguments for intrinsic value assume this
fact/value gap, their diverse attempts to bridge this same gap are necessarily
arbitrary and unconvincing.[2]
The Hegelian alternative that Kisner proposes is to see organic life as having
an inherent logic such that it is irreducible to mechanism and cannot be
appropriately or rationally treated as mere stuff or as a mere means to human
ends.
Accordingly, Kisner writes, Ôlife É cannot be
adequately conceived in terms of purely mechanical processes and É it is
ontologically inappropriate to treat it as if it were a mere mechanism [or] a
mere means to an end that is external to itÕ. The categories (that is, the ontological
principles) of mechanism undermine themselves: the mechanical-chemical sphere
proves to be more than can be accounted for under mechanistic categories. The
mechanical-chemical sphere proves to be, in truth, life, so that life is not
mechanism plus some vital extra, but is mechanism as it proves to be more than itself.
Thus, despite involving no vital extra, life is irreducible to mechanism and
must be understood in its own terms. To reduce life to mechanism is to assume,
erroneously, that mechanical categories are sustainable and not
self-undermining.
Kisner carefully follows HegelÕs reconstruction
in his Logic of
how this self-undermining happens. Let me summarize his very clear account.
Indifferent, self-external mechanical objects prove to be not actually
self-subsistent and indifferent; this is because, as they are not
self-determining, they must be determined to be self-external by something
outside themselves, namely (at this stage of the dialectic) other mechanical
objects. Mechanical objects thus exist only in relation to others outside them
and as such they are now chemical, oscillating between being mutually external
and being united with one another. Externality thereby proves to be an aspect of self-determining chemical
processes. This brings us to the category of teleology, in which externality
seems to be a means external to the purposive processes that use it. Yet actually
these external means are constituted by those processes, which are objectifying
themselves, purposively alienating themselves into mechanical-chemical shape.
With self-objectification, we reach life.
Because life is self-objectifying, it exists as
a living body. This embodies the conflict between lifeÕs unity as a single
process and its dispersal into bodily multiplicity. In sensibility the organism
returns to unity, but its internal conflict is thereby lost. The organism
therefore must re-confront its externality as something genuinely outside it
– an outer environment different from it, and then another living being
(because the organism must confront that which is outside it as implicitly its own, the same as it). The living being,
then, is necessarily one amongst others in a shared environment. But the
otherness by which the organism is now surrounded pains it insofar as it is in
principle self-same. It needs to reproduce itself as a unity by way of the
other. Therefore the organism assimilates other beings, and determines how
other objects mechanically-chemically affect it. The organism shapes its own
environment. And because that organism has proved to be, in truth, one amongst
similar others sharing a habitat – i.e. to be a member of a species
– that organism must reproduce itself as the species (e.g. it must reproduce sexually,
in the case of many organisms). But, because it is a self-external unity, the
organism reproduces its species-unity only in the form of another particular,
finite individual. In life, species and individual remain in dissension.
This ontology of life has ethical implications,
Kisner argues. Firstly, as rational beings we must follow the necessity of
reason; and to do so is to be self-determining, genuinely free as opposed to a
mere maker of arbitrary choices. Following the necessity of reason, we must
grasp life in its irreducibility, and as, in truth, species. Secondly, as
self-determining beings we must act in ways, and must cultivate habits and have
social institutions, that embody our rationality and hence that treat life appropriately
to its being, hence not as a mere means or a set of indifferent external
objects. Our self-determination, then, requires that we act
non-anthropocentrically. This does not mean that our obligations to life are
grounded, anthropocentrically after all, in our own necessity of being rational,
of fidelity to our own rational essence. Kisner ingeniously argues that our
duty to ourselves as rational beings is a duty to grasp being as it is and,
within that, to know and respond to life as it really is. We are to treat life as life for
its own sake, because to be the rational knowers that we are we have to treat
life as the life
that it is.
So, we have obligations to life, but since life
is in truth species, our obligations are to preserve species, not necessarily
single individuals: these may be sacrificed to the species (contrary to some individualistic
animal-rights theories). This consequence follows from our grasp of the
species/individual dissension that inheres in life: to treat life as it is to
treat its species-being as in partial conflict with, and if necessary as trumping,
its individual-being. We are also obliged to preserve habitats and biological
diversity as the external body of life – not as living beingsÕ external
means to their own continuation but as part of life, the self-external shape in which life itself
is objectified. In his Philosophy of Nature, Hegel characterizes the entire earth as self-externalized
life: ÔLife, as only the immediate idea, is É outside itself [au§er sich], non-life [Nicht-Leben], only the corpse of the living
process, the organism as totality of lifelessly existing, mechanical and
physical natureÕ.[3] Thus
although under KisnerÕs approach we have no obligations to non-living nature, very
little is thereby lost, because the scope of ÔlifeÕ includes much that we would
ordinarily, but irrationally, categorize as non-living – as Hegel has it,
non-life is an aspect of the entire life process.
As Kisner concedes, if this approach is
Hegelian in the sense of being the logical consequence of HegelÕs account of
life in his Logic,
it is not the road actually traveled by Hegel in his Elements of the Philosophy
of Right. On the
contrary, Hegel insists in that work that living beings are external means to
the human end of embodying freedom in private property, and that the only
obligations that human subjects have are towards other human beings and not
towards non-human living beings or any other aspect of life. But, Kisner
argues, with this insistence Hegel betrays his own thought. In the Logic, as Kisner cites, Hegel says that
when something acts on a living being mechanically – or, by implication,
teleologically, as a finite means – Ôit is not acting on it as on a living beingÕ (my emphasis). And
yet, Hegel also says (and as Kisner also quotes), ÔA person has as his
substantive end the right of putting his will into any and every thing É
because it has no such end in itselfÕ – and these ÔthingsÕ include
non-human living things, explicitly. So, Kisner concludes, Hegel has betrayed his own thought. The
implication seems to be that HegelÕs Philosophy of Right would need very extensive revision
to make it genuinely Hegelian by taking account of human obligations to life.
But a problem arises here. For Hegel, of
course, the Philosophy of Right is not merely a normative account of the right way to structure the
social world. It is also a descriptive account of the social structures –
private property, the nuclear family, civil society, the nation-state –
that Hegel saw emerging in modern European societies. Indeed, as a descriptive
account it is still largely accurate. Nuclear families, civil society, private
property and nation-states (globalization notwithstanding) are still with us.
They are still the Ôbasic structureÕ of Western societies. Moreover, it is
still the case that, in fact, these social institutions embody only inter-human
rights and obligations and that they are premised on the assumption that
non-human living and non-living beings are mere means to the realization of
human freedom. Hegel described this feature of these institutions, and he
described it accurately. For example, the fact is that our work and family
lives relying on us treating oil as a means for driving cars and running
machinery, or at best as a resource to be conserved for future generations. We
certainly do not treat the chemical stratum of the earth as part of the
objectified body of life as a whole and, as such, as something that cannot
appropriately be treated as a mere external means.
But perhaps, in consistency, Hegel should not
have argued that the social institutions he saw emerging in modern Europe were
the embodiment of human freedom and rationality. Yet that argument is
fundamental to his project as a social-political philosopher. As Michael
Hardimon has put it, Hegel seeks to show us that our modern social world
– at least in its essential, incipient kernel – is objectively a
home for us, a place where we can be at home in otherness and so be free. We
may feel alienated (entfremdet) from
this world, but this is subjective and not objective alienation: objectively,
our social world is a home, even if this truth is not transparent to us.[4]
If we follow KisnerÕs argument, though, then we
are objectively
alienated from ourselves in this social world. This world does not
appropriately institutionalize our freedom, that is, our rational
self-determination that crucially includes our obligation as rational thinking
beings to grasp life in its own irreducible logic and to act and live
consistently with that grasp of life. Instead, our modern social world
constrains us to be unfree, to act in accordance with ways of thinking about
and of treating living beings which our own rationality tells us are false.
On KisnerÕs reading of Hegel, then, he should
to be consistent have said that objectively we are not at home in the world. Somewhat
like Marx, albeit for different reasons, Hegel should have said that we are
objectively alienated. Presumably, also like Marx, he should have identified
some locus in the existing social world of a nascent more consistent
rationality and ethos with the potential to transform society and end our
objective alienation (equivalent to MarxÕs proletariat). Perhaps this locus
would be certain of our everyday life-world practices – recycling,
composting, re-using materials, insulating houses.
But could this possibly be a Hegelian approach?
For Hegel, the aim of showing that we are objectively at home in our social
world – or at least that that world has the essential lineaments of a
place where we can be at home – is fundamental. We therefore have to question
KisnerÕs argument that HegelÕs positions in the Philosophy of Right represent a failure of consistency
on his part. Consider that, for Hegel, life never succeeds in unifying itself.
Species and individuals remain in dissension (as Kisner himself says), and
within each living body unity and material plurality remain in dissension too.
Thus, Hegel claims, nature is the sphere of division between unity and material
plurality, and even natureÕs highest form, life, cannot totally dissolve this
division. Mind, however, does overcome this division through rational thought,
in which conceptual universals comprehensively encompass sensory particulars,
and through the construction of social institutions that embody human freedom
as rational self-determination.
If life is the truth of mechanism, then equally
mind is the truth of life. Mind is the self-differentiating unity that life is
in principle but fails fully to be. Ontologically higher than mechanism, life
is nonetheless ontologically below mind. Or so, at least, Hegel believes. But
these beliefs imply that relative to mind, non-minded living beings – that is,
non-human living beings and non-human life in all its aspects – do not
count as having their ends in themselves. This is because, compared to mind, non-human
life forms fail to fully realize their own purposiveness in their materiality
– to fully integrate their unity and their corporeal plurality. But
ultimately, as rational beings, we must grasp life precisely in comparison to
mind, as relatively undeveloped compared to the mind that life in its
self-undermining turns out to be. Consequently, Hegel can consistently claim that to treat
life as it really is – as life, irreducible to mechanism – is also
to treat life as ontologically inferior to human mind and therefore is, in
practice, to treat non-human life as a mere means to human purposes, not an end
in itself or bearer of inherent worth. Relative to human beings, life has no
rights.
I say this not to endorse these Hegelian views,
but so as to acknowledge that with respect to environmental issues HegelÕs
thought is not unequivocally constructive. As I argued, although in a somewhat
different way, in Petrified Intelligence, Hegel opens up possibilities for engagement
with environmental ethics at the ontological or metaphysical level of his
thought – including, as Kisner shows, by thinking life ontologically as
an end in itself. But Hegel closes down these possibilities at the level of his
moral-political philosophy. Contrary to Kisner, though, I think that this
closure reflects deep features of HegelÕs philosophical thinking, not a mere
failure to follow his own arguments through. This does not make him the enemy
of nature that he is sometimes made out to be. But it does mean that HegelÕs
relation to environmentalism is inescapably ambiguous.
Alison Stone, Lancaster University
[1] Richard Velkley, review of Songsuk Susan Hahn, Contradiction in Motion: Hegel's Organic Conception of Life and Value, in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2008.04.22 (http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=12943)
[2] In this connection Kisner criticises my own argument that, for Hegel, intrinsic value (or goodness) inheres in practical rationality and the latter is a dimension in all natural beings (in my Petrified Intelligence: Nature in HegelÕs Philosophy, Albany: SUNY Press, 2004, esp. ch. 6). As Kisner notes, this argument attributes to Hegel belief in a division between natureÕs rational and material sides. In partial defence of my earlier work, I will be arguing in this response that Hegel does indeed uphold such a division when he characterises life as self-external, and that this characterisation is crucially connected to his denial of human obligations to nature or to non-human living beings.
[3] Hegel, EnzykopŠdie der philosophischen Wissenschaften II, Werke 9 (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970), ¤337.
[4] Michael O. Hardimon, HegelÕs Social Philosophy: The Project of Reconciliation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), esp. pp. 119-22.