German
Romantic and Idealist Conceptions of Nature
I.
Recent interpreters
of German Idealism and Early German Romanticism differ on whether these
movements are discontinuous or continuous. According to Manfred Frank (1997),
they are discontinuous because the Idealists affirm, while the Romantics deny,
that the ground of our being is fully accessible to our intellects. According
to Frederick Beiser (2002), on the other hand, these movements are continuous
because both Romantics and Idealists hold that this ground – the universe
as a whole, or the ÒabsoluteÓ – is
intelligible to us (via a form of aesthetic intuition). In this article I will
help to clarify how continuous these movements are by turning to a different
aspect of them: their approaches to nature. Both the Jena Romantics and the
German Idealists advance metaphysical theories of what nature is and of how
natural processes and kinds are organised. In particular, both Romantics and
Idealists hold that nature is an organic, self-organising, whole, and that
nature in its self-organising capacity prefigures and makes possible human
autonomy. However, the Romantics tend (as I shall show here with reference to
Novalis) to see human autonomy as
merely a higher-level version of the self-organisation of nature[1]
– a naturalist conception of autonomy which Hegel (among the German
Idealists) rejects, so that he constructs a revised account of nature that
supports an anti-naturalist view of human autonomy. Thus, taking Novalis and
Hegel to represent German Romanticism and Idealism respectively, we may
conclude that these movements are partly continuous, in respect of their
approaches to nature, but partly discontinuous, in that they develop these
approaches in naturalist and anti-naturalist directions respectively.
To explain these points, I first need to
clarify what Hegel and Novalis mean by ÒnatureÓ. For Hegel, nature (the subject
matter of his Philosophy of Nature)
is distinct both from (1) what is human or
humanly created and structured (these forming the subject matter of HegelÕs Philosophy
of Mind) and from (2) the general
ontological principles (described in his Logic), such as causality or becoming, that apply to both
humanity and nature. On the other hand Novalis, as we will see, tends to take
ÒnatureÓ to encompass everything, and to be synonymous with the universe as a
whole. But, at the same time, Novalis thinks that the universe develops
organically and is a large-scale organism. He also assumes, as we will see,
that any organism is ÒnaturalÓ (rather than artificial) because organisms make
themselves according to internal plans, rather than being made according to
externally imposed plans as artefacts are. He therefore understands the
universe to be ÒnatureÓ in this more specific sense too: that it is an organic,
self-developing whole.
Secondly, I need
to clarify what I mean by ÒnaturalismÓ in relation to German Idealism and
Romanticism. What counts as ÒnaturalismÓ is increasingly controversial, but I
shall adopt a fairly traditional understanding of naturalism as encompassing a
family of positions that deny the existence of any supernatural existents and
that therefore treat human beings as completely natural creatures, including in
respect of capacities (for rational thought, artistic creation, moral agency)
which, at least until the late 1700s, would usually have been thought to derive
from some uniquely non- or supernatural element setting human beings above
animals, often the immortal soul. ÒNatureÓ in naturalism is whatever the
empirical sciences understand it to be, generally an order of entities and
events that are causally related in law-governed ways. Now, most scholars of
the German Idealists (see, e.g., Kemp Smith, 1920; Gardner, 2007; Pinkard,
2002; Pippin, 1999, 2005) have held that they are non-naturalists because they
adhere to a Kantian conception of autonomy and normativity. On this conception,
I fail to exercise autonomy if I merely choose between several possible courses
of action based on my desires. Rather, to be autonomous I must determine for
myself what principles of action are to be authoritative for me, and I must
make this determination on the basis of my rationality, which is impersonal and
shared with all other rational beings. On this view, then, the German Idealists
are non-naturalist because they hold that we must determine practical (and also
epistemic) norms from our rationality, in doing which we abstract from nature,
in particular from our desires and from the causal order of nature of which
these desires are part.[2]
Insofar as this Kantian conception of autonomy and normativity is common
currency among the German Romantics too, it seems that they too must be
non-naturalist.
But this view that
German Idealism and Romanticism are non-naturalist must be complicated when we
take into account their approaches to nature.[3]
Since, for the Idealists and Romantics, philosophy must be systematic,[4]
our understanding of nature must be continuous with our understanding that
human beings are capable of determining normative validity from within
themselves qua rational, and so our
understanding of nature must be such as to explain this human capacity.[5]
The aim is to explain this capacity in a way that preserves KantÕs
(anti-naturalist) idea that we determine what is normative from our rationality
and not from our desires, from which (for Kant) we are to prescind qua rational. Now, Novalis tries to effect this
explanation by reconceiving nature as (pace Kant) not simply an order of items related by
efficient causation, but as already exercising a form of rational
self-organisation which is a less developed form of the capacity for rational
self-determination that we find in human agents. On this view, human autonomy
is simply a higher-level realisation of natureÕs general power of
self-organisation. By taking this view, Novalis hopes to preserve the idea that
we determine normative validity from our rationality and not from our desires,
but he abandons KantÕs idea that we thereby abstract from nature, instead
claiming that we thereby realise
natureÕs rationality to a higher level. In this sense, Novalis puts forward a
naturalistic reconception of Kantian autonomy.
It might be
objected that this cannot possibly be a naturalistic project, because any idea
that nature organises itself rationally must be supernaturalist (Gardner, 2007, p. 46). This depends on
how one defines ÒsupernaturalismÓ. Generally Novalis does not believe in
mysterious, occult powers that transcend the laws of nature. Moreover, his
approach to nature cannot be counted as supernaturalist simply on the grounds
that he attributes purposefulness to nature, since this is consistent with his
seeing nature as a causal order, albeit one within which some causes are telic
rather than efficient. Nor can NovalisÕs view of nature rightly be counted as
supernaturalist on the grounds that it diverges from the empirical sciences,
since Novalis thought that his view was consistent with, indeed required by,
the empirical sciences of his time, which seemed to have readmitted forms of
teleological explanation and surpassed Cartesian mechanism (see Richards,
2002). At least by the scientific standards of his time, then, NovalisÕs view
of nature counts as naturalistic.
The problem with
NovalisÕs naturalistic reconception of Kantian autonomy, though, is that
contrary to his own intentions he fails to preserve KantÕs idea that when we
rationally determine what is normative we prescind from our desires. Because
for Novalis our rationality is a higher-level development of natureÕs
self-organisation, our rationality is also a higher-level development of the
self-organisation of our – sensing, desiring – bodies: our rationality emerges from our bodies and desires
rather than constituting an abstraction from them. Novalis is unhappy with his
own departure from Kant on this point, which leads him to revise his views of
nature and autonomy so that they become inconsistent overall.
Hegel, for his
part, seeks to systematise Romantic Naturphilosophie. The way in which he does this preserves a Kantian,
anti-naturalist, conception of autonomy. Thus, Hegel offers an account of how humanityÕs capacity for rational
self-determination emerges from (a primitive form of rational self-organisation
within) nature but is, nonetheless, non-natural, involving a ÒbreakÓ with
nature. Yet this possibility of human agents to ÒbreakÓ with nature is itself
prepared by nature: nature is, essentially, self-negating or self-cancelling.
In systematising Romantic Naturphilosophie, then, Hegel strips it of the naturalist dimension that Novalis had
given it.
II.
Novalis develops his conception of
nature in his draft encyclopedia, the Allgemeine Brouillon (1798-99). Here he explores correspondences between
different sciences and their explanatory principles. He surmises that the
sciences exhibit these correspondences because their objects of study also
correspond – there are, he writes, Òrelations – similarities
– identitiesÓ between all natural kinds and processes (Novalis, 2007,
#233, p. 34).[6] Any given
kind or process recapitulates the structure of many other kinds and processes
to either a higher (more intricately developed) or lower (less developed)
level. For example, youth (allegedly) corresponds to fluidity, age to rigidity;
women correspond to oxygen, men to flame; sensing recapitulates the process of
devouring food at a higher, more psychical, level (Novalis, 2007, #97, p. 16;
#117, p. 19; #273, p. 40).
Novalis concludes
that nature forms a whole system of interrelated kinds and processes. He
writes: ÒEach individual life-process is determined by the universal
life-process, the natural system of an individual is determined both by the
other individual natural systems and by the higher, universal
system—ultimately by the natural system of the universe, insofar as this
equally determines both of the formerÓ (Novalis, 2007, #460, p. 76). Each
individual entity or process is as it is because it instantiates its kind (i.e.
it is determined by the relevant universal), and each kind is the way it is
because of its myriad relations of correspondence to other kinds (i.e. it is
Òdetermined by other natural systemsÓ). Ultimately, each entity, process and
kind is as it is because of its relations to all the others; each thing (Ding) is as it is because its place in the whole
conditions (bedingt) it to be so.[7]
All natural things therefore form the Ònatural system of the universeÓ, a whole
that is not merely the sum of independently existing things but constitutes
these things – a synthetic rather than composite whole.[8]
Novalis defines this whole system as Òthe absoluteÓ: ÒOnly the All is
absoluteÓ; ÒIn every moment, in every
appearance, the whole is operating. ... It is all, it is over all; In whom we live, breathe and have our beingÓ; ÒThe
universe is the absolute subject, or the totality of all predicatesÓ (Novalis,
2003, #454, p. 145; #462, p. 147; 2007, #633, p. 113).
Novalis concludes
that the absolute or the Òstructure of the worldÓ is equally Òthe organism of the worldÓ (Novalis, 2007, #503, p. 90) – a
cosmic organism – a fanciful-seeming idea that reflects his reliance on
KantÕs conception of the organism. According to KantÕs Critique of
Teleological Judgement, the parts of an
organism are so functionally interconnected that they must be understood to be
constituted by the whole of which they are parts, and as constituting its own
parts the organism must be understood to be a self-organising whole (Kant,
1987, pp. 248-255). Applying this to the Òuniversal system of natureÓ, Novalis
writes: ÒEvery phenomenon is a limb in an immeasurable chain—which
comprehends all phenomena as
limbsÓ (Novalis, 1975, vol. 3, #140, p. 574). That is, this theory must treat
all natural processes and kinds as ÒlimbsÓ of a large-scale organism growing
from within itself, explaining how each limb derives from the developmental trajectory
of the whole organism.
As we see, Novalis
tends to equate the universe as a whole – the absolute – with
nature, speaking of the natural system
of the universe. For Novalis, this system coincides with nature because (as he
says) all phenomena belong within
this system, including all phenomena of the human mind. Because for Novalis
these phenomena realise the self-organising powers of nature, they remain
within nature, which therefore is all-encompassing. For Novalis, then,
metaphysics – interpreted as the study of the absolute – coincides
with philosophy of nature; hence the metaphysics of the Brouillon is equally an examination of the empirical natural
sciences.
NovalisÕs
ÒorganicistÓ metaphysics may seem to regress to pre-Kantian metaphysical speculation
compared against the anti-foundationalism of his Fichte Studies (1795-96), which stresses the limits to what we can
know. On Manfred FrankÕs (1997) well-known interpretation of this
anti-foundationalist position, Novalis holds that we can only feel but not know
the ground of our being (the absolute), although our feeling keeps compelling
us to attempt to know it; in these attempts, we only learn more about finite
things, but as a result we progressively systematise our knowledge of the
finite. Since the resulting system of knowledge but does not derive from any
certain first principle (such as a principle conferring knowledge of the
absolute), each element of knowledge in the system lacks certainty and is
always liable to be falsified or require revision, so that we cannot bring the
system to definitive completion.
Despite its
initial appearance of immodesty, NovalisÕs metaphysics in the Brouillon is compatible with anti-foundationalism. For
Novalis, our knowledge that the world is an organic whole is not a first
principle from which we may deduce knowledge of everything. Rather, we learn
that the world is a whole by reflecting philosophically on (and trying to
systematise) empirical scientific findings, from which, too, we must learn
about the particular processes and kinds that the whole generates. Since we are
not deducing these scientific findings from a first principle, they never
obtain certainty; hence our process of systematising them must be ongoing, so
that our knowledge of how the absolute develops cannot become complete or
final. Thus, we can interpret NovalisÕs famous statement ÒWe seek the absolute everywhere and only ever find thingsÓ (Novalis, 1997, p. 23) as asserting that we
cannot know the absolute in the specific sense that, although we can
provisionally conclude from the correspondences between the sciences that there
is an absolute, we can never have complete or definitive knowledge about the
absolute given the fallibility of our scientific knowledge.
I noted that
Novalis equates the absolute with nature because he intends his organicist
metaphysics to include a naturalistic account of the human mind. As part of
this, Novalis intends to derive human autonomy from nature, even though he
understands human autonomy, following Kant, as the capacity to determine
normative principles from reason and not from desire. Novalis approaches the
task of deriving human autonomy from nature by attributing to nature a kind of
ÒfreedomÓ that prefigures human autonomy.
III.
Novalis claims that insofar as the
absolute organises itself, it exercises self-determination: it gives itself a
determinate form solely from within itself, not under constraints or conditions
imposed by exterior entities or forces. ÒNature [is] at once independent and self-modifyingÓ;
ÒThe universe is the absolute subject É In this its É organisation is already containedÓ (Novalis, 2007, #50, p. 7; #633, p. 113) –
that is, the universeÕs organisation is contained and emanates from within it.
That the absolute determines its shape from within itself follows from its
being living, assuming something to be living if it grows and shapes itself
guided by internal principles of development (whereas an artefact takes shape
under the guidance of external principles: the ÒblueprintÓ in the artisanÕs
mind).
Novalis adds:
ÒLife is freedom of natureÓ (2007, #172, p. 27). The absolute is free qua living, then, because its development is directed by
a telos internal to it. The
absolute is free not in escaping causal determination, but because its development
is determined solely by final causation, the purpose affecting the absolute
from within it, not by efficient causation, which would act on the absolute
from outside it. Whereas any living being (e.g. an acorn) has a telos to become a finite thing of a specific kind (e.g. an
oak tree), the absolute as the non-finite whole cannot have a telos of that type. The only telos the absolute can have is that of becoming every
finite thing and of becoming the system of relations between finite things.
NovalisÕs account
of the absoluteÕs telos gives him a way
to understand why the absolute develops into the natural kinds and processes
that it does. The absolute, for him, develops by alternately differentiating
and reintegrating itself. First the absolute develops into a plurality of
finite things, then it strives to reintegrate these – to systematically
interconnect them so that it will exist as the whole (system) that includes
them. If the absolute assumes the shape of the system binding any finite set of
things, though, then the absolute has again become finite; hence it must
differentiate itself into further things, then seek their reintegration, and so
on ad infinitum. Novalis found
evidence of this differentiating-and-reintegrating pattern in, for instance, contemporary
chemistry, in which it seemed that different entities are compelled by some
inner force (the absolute) to unite, then to separate again, and then to
re-enter further chemical cycles.
As I have said, in
developing his teleological picture of the absolute Novalis aims to see nature
as prefiguring human autonomy understood in terms of rational
self-determination. A telos is a
normative standard for development, such that something is good – of its
kind, or good simpliciter, in the
case of the absolute – in proportion as it realises that telos. Nature, then, is subject to a norm in that it both
ought to and does obey its internal standard that prescribes that it become a
systematically integrated set of finite things. The systematic integration so prescribed
can be seen as a harbinger or primitive form of rationality. To that extent
natureÕs purpose is to become rational, and nature is rational in proportion as
it realises that purpose. If rational thinking on the part of human beings is
then seen as a high-level development of natureÕs power of systematic
integration (something Novalis will go on to claim), and if we are autonomous
when our rationality determines what beliefs or principles count as normative
for us, then nature indeed prefigures and makes possible human autonomy.
Puzzlingly,
though, Novalis sometimes introduces an alternative picture of nature as a kind
of entirely groundless bursting-forth. He does so because of a worry that
causal explanations cannot appropriately be applied to the absolute, as opposed
to finite things. ÒThe opposite of all
determination is freedom. The absolute
opposite is freedomÓ (Novalis, 2003, #284,
p. 99). Compressed in this statement are the thoughts that freedom consists in
the absence of causal determination, and that the absolute precedes and is the
source of all determinate objects and their causal relations, so that the
absolute is outside all causal considerations and is in that sense ÒfreeÓ. Its
development must be utterly groundless: no explanatory factor, external or
internal, may be invoked to account for the fact or the manner of its
development. The absolute does what it does inexplicably. If, on the other
hand, the absolute developed from its own telos, then its development would be causally determined by an element within it;
something Novalis now wants to avoid. It is not clear, though, that his
motivation for avoiding this is sound; there is a relevant distinction between
explaining why the absolute develops in the particular way that it does and explaining
the absolute (that is, asking why there is a universe at all).
Still, the
alternative, irrationalist view of nature that Novalis at times proposes has
implications for autonomy. On this view, nature does not merely have an inbuilt
telos to pursue self-integration;
rather, nature determines for itself that it ought to pursue systematic
integration, in the sense that nature adopts this purpose without cause,
conferring normative force on this purpose in so adopting it. Yet nature adopts
the purpose not from reason but, specifically, without any reason. Inasmuch as nature prefigures human
autonomy, the autonomy so prefigured now involves not determining normativity
from reason but, rather, conferring normative authority quite arbitrarily.
Thus, NovalisÕs idea that nature develops groundlessly supports a view of human
autonomy as arbitrary self-legislation (see Section 4).[9]
Novalis sometimes
weaves this irrationalist view of nature together with his usual rationalist
view. In notes from late 1799, he claims that nature both follows laws –
it develops according to regular and predictable patterns – and acts from
its ÒwillÓ (Wille). He clarifies that
nature both has Òno willÓ and has Òa particular willÓ (Novalis, 1975, 3: #291,
601). That is: nature follows laws, develops in a regular way, because it
unfolds from its inner telos; yet
again, nature must be free not merely in developing from its own telos but, more strongly, in having free ÒwillÓ, i.e.
developing however it wills with no ground of its decisions. Novalis again
oscillates between the two views when he describes natureÕs structure as both
ÒimmeasurableÓ (unerme§lich) and
ÒmeasurableÓ (Novalis, 2007, #633, p. 113). That is, we can anticipate and
predict how nature develops in that it develops from its telos; then again, we may venture no predictions because
nature just bursts forth without rhyme or reason.
IV.
Let us now look in more detail at
the conception of human autonomy that Novalis derives from his usual
understanding of nature as a rationally self-organising whole.
NovalisÕs view
that nature tends towards systematic self-integration leads him to see the
human mind as an integrated system that is the highest realisation of the
self-organisation of nature. ÒThinking,
É is surely nothing else but the finest evolution of the plastic forces – it is simply the
general force of Nature raised to the nth dignityÓ (Novalis, 2007, #114, p. 189). For Novalis, human beings achieve their supremely
high level of mental organisation by imposing concepts on their sensations and
uniting their concepts in judgements. Novalis is extending KantÕs view that
concepts and judgements are not merely mental representations that we in fact
have but rules for how we must think in order to give our experience intelligible
structure. For Novalis, concepts and judgements are normative insofar as they
make our experience coherent and integrated. (By which token we also become
conscious, for Novalis, who takes it that to be conscious is simply to have
experience as a specifically cognitive state.) We organise our mental life,
too, by adjusting our judgements into a coherent system. NovalisÕs
anti-foundationalist view is that we strive to adjust our beliefs relative to
one another so that they form as coherent a system as possible. This picture of
mind implies that I ought to hold any belief (or, by extension, practical
principle) inasmuch as it coheres with my other beliefs and principles and with
those that other people hold, if they too employ the standard of intra- and inter-subjective
coherence.
Now, whereas for
Kant the normativity of concepts and judgements makes them non-natural, rules that we make for ourselves – as
we ought – rather than being determined by nature to follow, for Novalis
nature remains the source of the normativity of beliefs and principles. These
are normative insofar as they exhibit and promote coherence, which itself is
normative because a coherent system of thought would be the highest realisation
of the self-organisation of nature, where it is good for nature to become as
self-organised as possible because doing so is natureÕs telos. So although for Novalis we ascertain what is
normative from reason (by working out what is coherent), our rationality
confers normativity only because this rationality realises natureÕs telos. Reason is the source of normativity, but this is
because reason realises nature, not (pace Kant) because it prescinds from nature.
Novalis has tried,
then, to derive the human capacity for rational self-determination from nature,
in the process reconceiving this capacity as a power to abstract from desire
but not from nature, which is itself
rational. Yet it is not clear that Novalis can see the human capacity for
rational self-determination as emerging from nature without also seeing this
capacity as emerging from human bodies, in such a way that human beings, in
exercising rationality, after all are drawing or building on their desires
rather than abstracting from those desires. NovalisÕs doctrine of Òmagical
idealismÓ, touched upon at regular intervals throughout the Brouillon, illustrates this.
Magical idealism
is the rather bizarre doctrine that we should gain control of our Òouter
sensesÓ – the senses by which we are affected by and receive input from
the outer world – so that we can perceive the world as we (in some sense)
choose. We are to gain this control by following particular medicinal practices
– ensuring the right balance between eating, drinking and fasting and
between exercise and rest. Novalis is influenced by John BrownÕs (1735-88)
medical theory, on which illness results from either excessive or insufficient
ÒirritabilityÓ, i.e. excitation. By habitually maintaining the right diet and
level of exercise we can regulate how much excitation our outer senses receive,
and so what secretions our sense-organs transmit around our bodies, and so what
passions we feel. With the right level of passions, the judgements that
structure our perceptions will be correspondingly balanced and our perceptions
will therefore cohere with one another, so that in that sense we will be
perceiving as we (would ideally) choose. The better our sensuous, bodily nature
is integrated the more we will attain coherence at the mental level. Because
the mind is the body to a higher level, the more the body realises natureÕs telos of integration, the more authority that telos – in the higher form of reason – obtains
over the mind. Thus, if we can determine norms from our rationality, this is
not because of any power to prescind from our desires, but rather because we
already have rationally structured sets of bodily desires, structures from
which a further power of rational self-determination arises.
But Novalis is
unhappy to have moved away from the original Kantian idea that normativity
derives from reason as opposed to
desire. He therefore tries to restore the idea that human beings determine what
is normative in a departure from what is natural, including from human desires.
But for Novalis it cannot be the case that we so determine what is normative by
exercising reason, because for him reason just is nature to a higher power. So we can only determine
normativity in departure from nature if we make this determination not
from reason but from its absence, i.e.
quite arbitrarily. To be autonomous, then, is to arbitrarily legislate certain
principles to oneself, as opposed to having their authority prescribed by (the
rational system of) nature. These thoughts push Novalis towards (and are
manifested in) a second version of magical idealism. On this version, magical
idealist medicinal practices enable one to sense things entirely at will: to
sense just what one chooses to sense, voluntarily – indeed, he says,
arbitrarily (Novalis, 2007, #1075, p. 181). Whatever data impinge on oneÕs
outer senses, the magical idealist can perceive something wholly or partly
different from those data, and can impose on outer events whatever significance
or construction s/he chooses. This reflects NovalisÕs view that to be
autonomous, I must legislate to myself quite at whim, and totally independently
of nature, including independently of the sensations that my body, as an item
in the natural world, receives. Thus, I must legislate at whim even with regard
to my perceptions – I must determine what I perceive arbitrarily . However,
Novalis qualifies this claim: I ought to give myself perceptions of a kind that
manifest their status as the
products of my arbitrary choice. These perceptions are of miraculous or
wondrous events that contravene laws of nature (the staple of fairy-tales, e.g.
a prince suddenly changing into a pig or vice versa), which therefore manifest the fact that they result
from the selfÕs power to determine the content of perception quite as it
wishes, without regard to the causal relations that hold within the system of
nature (Novalis, 2007, #730, p. 135).
Novalis tries to
combine this version of magical idealism with his preceding naturalistic
version by saying that by engaging in
appropriate medicinal practices we become able to arbitrarily determine what we
perceive. This attempted synthesis fails: since exercising arbitrary control
over oneÕs senses requires that one legislate without regard to the purposes of
nature, the adequacy with which one realises those purposes at a bodily level
cannot be relevant to whether one can exercise this control.
Moreover,
NovalisÕs interpretation of autonomy as arbitrariness has difficulty accounting
for (what he sees as) the binding, obligatory validity of the norms we
legislate to ourselves. If we do so quite arbitrarily, then presumably we can
authorise and de-authorise norms at whim.[10]
Yet this interpretation ties in to – and supports – NovalisÕs view
that nature develops groundlessly. So far, this interpretation of autonomy has
seemed anti-naturalist, since on this interpretation we assign norms to
ourselves as opposed to being given them by nature. But this interpretation
might not be anti-naturalist if nature is a wholly groundless bursting-forth,
as Novalis has also proposed: for in that case, by legislating norms for themselves
quite arbitrarily, human beings realise
nature understood as that which forms itself groundlessly. Ultimately, though,
this position is still anti-naturalist. For on this position, nature itself is
not solely a causal order but is also the uncaused – ÒfreeÓ – power
preconditioning all causally related events. But because ÒnatureÓ in naturalism
is the nature of the empirical sciences, that is, nature as the totality of
causally related, law-governed events, Novalis has given the name ÒnatureÓ to a
force that counts as non-natural – indeed, supernatural – by
naturalist standards.[11]
So the ÒnatureÓ that human beings realise by acting arbitrarily is actually a non-natural power to act groundlessly.
Novalis has
succumbed to these conflicting views because he has two incompatible aims: to
give a naturalist account of human autonomy as emerging from rational
self-organisation within nature, and to preserve KantÕs idea that autonomy
requires abstraction from desire. It fell to the German Idealists, and Hegel above
all, to render Romantic metaphysics consistent and rid it of these conflicts.[12]
Let us see how Hegel achieves this in his mature Philosophy of Nature.
V.
Hegel seeks to retain the
non-naturalist view that autonomy requires abstraction from desire, but also to
explain via his Naturphilosophie how our
capacity so to abstract emerges out of the rational self-organisation of
nature. How, though, can he give Naturphilosophie this role without following Novalis into naturalism
and thereby abandoning the opposition between reason and desire? HegelÕs
solution is that human reason and autonomy must be understood specifically as
resulting from the self-supersession of nature, natureÕs Òextinguish[ing]
itself, É consum[ing] itself like a phoenix in order to emerge É rejuvenated as
mindÓ (Hegel, 1970, vol. 3, #376A, p. 212). Thus, although human autonomy is
essentially non-natural, its structure as non-natural is the result of
nature, qua self-superseding.
To understand
this, we first need to see that, like Novalis, Hegel regards all natural kinds
and processes as an interconnected system, in which each is a higher or lower
development of others. Unlike Novalis, Hegel aims to give a more-or-less
definitive account of where each particular natural kind or process belongs in
this systematic order. For instance, he treats magnetism as the lower-level
analogue of electrical processes, in turn the lower-level analogue of chemical
processes.
The overall
organisation of nature, according to Hegel, is into the lowest-level ÒmechanicalÓ
sphere, the higher-level ÒphysicalÓ sphere (in which magnetism, electricity and
chemistry, amongst other processes, belong), and the highest-level ÒorganicÓ
sphere. Thus, Hegel regards living beings – the earth inasmuch as it is a
complex and self-regulating system, plants, and animals, including human beings
– as the highest level of nature. Since Hegel regards the organic sphere
as only one part of nature, it might seem that, unlike Novalis, he does not
consider nature as a whole to be an organism. But this is not so. Like Novalis,
Hegel thinks that each natural thing is constituted as it is by its place in
the whole system of nature – each thing is as it is because it embodies
its kind, and each kind is as it is because of its location in the chain of
natural correspondences. Since the whole system is thus constitutive of its
parts, this system counts as organic and self-organising, according, again, to
the Kantian conception of a living being.
Much more than
Novalis, Hegel stresses that nature, as a whole system, organises itself in
accordance with the requirements of reason.
For Hegel, each natural kind contains an internal ÒcontradictionÓ (Widerspruch) to
which another natural kind provides the solution, while in turn succumbing to
an inner contradiction of its own which yet another kind resolves. For example,
Hegel regards space as internally ÒcontradictoryÓ on the grounds that it is a
whole composed of different spatial units, and yet these units are completely
distinctionless (Hegel, 1970, vol. 1, #254, p. 223). As this exemplifies, the
ÒcontradictionsÓ of which Hegel speaks may be better understood as internal
tensions or instabilities rather than literal, logical contradictions.[13]
Each natural kind contains an inner tension, then, and in each case Hegel
identifies another natural kind the inner structure of which is such that this
new kind can be seen as eliminating that preceding tension, so that he can
position the new kind as the immediately higher-level successor to the first
kind. He therefore claims that nature advances from its least to its most
developed form not in a Òsimple transitionÓ but through Òa series of stages
consisting of many momentsÓ (Hegel, 1971, #381A, p. 13).
Exactly how is
nature organising itself according to rational requirements here? The overall
organisation of nature is rational, because on each occasion that a
ÒcontradictionÓ or antagonism manifests itself in nature, a natural kind can be
found that embodies the resolution of that tension. (To HegelÕs mind, this exemplifies
rationality because it involves resolving contradictions; although we can say
that, by extension, removing instabilities or tensions is also a rational
activity.) So the picture Hegel appears to give us is not that nature itself
responds to rational requirements but that we – scientifically informed
philosophers – can reconstruct an order within nature such that nature
presents itself to us as satisfying our standards of rationality.
In the Philosophy
of Nature, though, Hegel pursues a stronger
account of natureÕs rationality, on which we can only identify rational order
within nature because nature, independently of us, is already organising itself
rationally. He explains:
Nature is to be
regarded as a system of stages, one
proceeding necessarily from the other and being the direct truth of that from
which it results. This is not to be thought of as a natural engendering of one out of the other however, but as
an engendering within the inner idea which constitutes the ground of nature.
(Hegel, 1970, vol. 1, #249, p. 212)
Nature, then, is rational in that
it is grounded in Òthe ideaÓ. Since Hegel defines and introduces his technical
concept of Òthe ideaÓ in his Encyclopaedia Logic, we can only understand what he means by the ideaÕs being the ground
of nature in relation to his Logic.
Firstly, the Logic examines our basic categories (see Houlgate 2007,
143-45). To simplify, the Logic
unfolds as we first show that some particular category is necessary for any
thought. Then we find that this category has limitations, such that we need an
additional category which provides the only possible – or, at least, the
best available – corrective to those limitations. Then we find that this
new category is also limited,
such that yet another category is required – and so on until we have
deduced a complete chain of categories or Òthought-determinationsÓ (Gedankenbestimmungen). Secondly, Hegel believes that these
Òthought-determinationsÓ are not only basic forms of thought but also basic
structures or ordering principles that organise objects as they exist
independently of our minds (Houlgate 2007, 150). For example, when he derives
the category of causality, he sees causality not only as a category with which
we must necessarily think but also a basic principle structuring all
mind-independent things in causal relations to one another (Hegel, 1991a,
#153-#154, pp. 227-30). Thus, Hegel claims to see the categories as not merely
subjective but also Òthe truth, objectivity, and actual being of É things
themselves. [The categories] resemble the Platonic ideas É which exist in
individual things as substantial generaÓ (Hegel, 1970, vol. 1, #246A, p. 200).
Late in his Logic, Hegel introduces the category that he calls Òthe
ideaÓ, which he defines as rational thought that fully organises and pervades
objective reality (Òthe absolute unity of concept and objectivityÓ; Hegel, 1991a, #213, p. 286). Yet according to
HegelÕs account all categories
organise objective reality. This indicates that rather than being a particular
new category, Òthe ideaÓ is simply the system of all the preceding categories,
a system that is rational because its component categories correct one
anotherÕs limitations. Moreover, the idea is this system of categories insofar
as it organises the objective world – it is an overarching rational order
that structures all real things.
It appears to
follow that nature is rational in that it is organised by this higher-level
ontological system, the idea. Yet this is still not quite HegelÕs position.
After all, he does not proceed in the Philosophy of Nature only by showing that each natural kind embodies some
rational structure as described in the Logic (although he does regularly suggest parallels
between natural kinds and logical structures). Rather, as we saw, he identifies
each natural kind as suffering from its own inner instability while also resolving an
instability in a preceding natural kind (as opposed to identifying each natural
kind as exemplifying a logical category that contains a given problem but also
resolves the problem in a preceding logical category). Hegel can only map
particular natural kinds onto particular logical categories in virtue of having
initially identified a series of instabilities and resolutions specific to
nature.
Hegel begins with
natureÕs own instabilities because of another aspect of his account of the
idea: that the idea ÒexternalisesÓ itself to produce nature (Hegel, 1970, vol.
1., #247, p. 205). By a kind of self-inversion or emptying-out of itself, the idea enters into the form of matter
(Hegel, 1970, vol. 1, #248R, p. 209). HegelÕs claim that matter is a
self-externalised form of the idea is strange, but has understandable
philosophical motivations. Having argued that a system of categories structures
material reality, Hegel has to explain why there is any material reality to
undergo categorial structuring – after all, his system is intended to be
presuppositionless, so he cannot simply assume that matter exists. Since the
only available explanans is the
idea, matter must be understood to emerge from the idea; but matter is partes
extra partes, inherently antithetical to
the centralising and unifying character of the idea (Hegel, 1971, #381A, p. 9);
the notion that the idea externalises, or becomes other to, itself distils
these points.[14]
The consequence of
these claims, though, is that for Hegel the lowest-level natural kind just is
matter itself. Hegel then understands the progression within nature as a
progression in which the idea gradually Òreturns to itselfÓ out of its self-externalisation
as matter. His thought is that in higher-level natural kinds, we discern the
operation of organising and unifying principles that are not simply material,
but rather give structure to matter. For example, in magnetism an integrating
principle is operative that draws different elements together; in chemistry,
again, an integrating principle draws different substances together; and
ultimately, in living beings, a non-material whole organises and constitutes
their various members.
So, for Hegel, nature
does not instantiate the idea as a structure that is essentially independent of
and unaffected by nature. Rather, the entirety of nature is the idea in a particular range of forms: first in
totally self-externalised form as matter, and then in an ascending series of
forms in which the idea progressively returns to itself by restoring
organisation to its own material forms. (Moreover, this means that the idea is
not only the system of logical and mental categories but also the system of
natural kinds.)
Because all
natural kinds are forms of the idea
(forms that combine self-externalisation and self-restoration in varied
proportions), Hegel understands the relations between natural kinds to be of
the same type as relations between the logical categories that are
non-self-externalised forms of the idea. When each logical category falls prey
to problems, the idea generates or enters into the form of the category that
will resolve that problem. (So the idea is not only the system of categories
– and of natural kinds – but also the organising force behind the
emergence of this system. This is because the idea, as a system or whole, is
synthetic, constituting its parts.) Likewise in nature, the idea existing in
the form of any given natural kind will, on becoming subject to an inner
instability, generate or enter into the particular natural kind that will
resolve that instability.[15]
Moreover, an
instability is generic to nature because nature is the idea existing in
material, or materially entangled, forms which are inappropriate to the ideaÕs
really non-material character. Ò[N]ature has É been regardedÓ – rightly,
for Hegel – Òas the ideaÕs falling short of itself, for in this external
shape the idea is inadequate to itselfÓ (Hegel, 1970, vol. 1, #248R, p. 209). Hence,
the entire natural progression whereby the idea increasingly returns to itself
is rational because that progression works to resolve natureÕs generic
instability. In this global case, as in the specific transitions within nature,
nature exhibits the rationality of the idea that it ultimately is.
Strange as HegelÕs
picture of nature is, it recognisably builds on the Romantic attempt to see
nature as rationally self-organising in a way that prefigures human autonomy.
But whereas for the Romantics (as we saw in the case of Novalis) nature
organises itself because it has a telos to
do so, for Hegel nature organises itself from reason. This is in the sense that nature enters into each of
its component kinds, and takes on the overall organisation that it does, in
order to resolve contra-rational instabilities. Together with his reconception
of nature as rational, Hegel entirely abandons the sometime Romantic idea that
nature develops quite groundlessly.
However, for Hegel
it is only possible for nature to give its structure to itself from reason
because nature is the idea (in self-externalised form). This fact enables
nature to form itself rationally because the idea is the principle –
operative not only in human thought but also throughout the world – that
shapes itself into successive structures in ways that resolve instabilities or
tensions in their predecessors: that is, the idea is the activity of
constructing or generating structures rationally. Whereas Novalis equated
nature with the absolute, then, for Hegel the idea – rational constructive activity as it
generates the system of ontological structures, natural kinds and mental
activities – is the absolute, the whole encompassing and constituting all
entities. Nature is only part of the absolute idea. Thus, Hegel systematises
the Romantic picture of nature by grounding nature in an underlying realm of
non-material rational agency: ÒIn time nature comes first, but the absolute prius is the ideaÓ (Hegel, 1970, vol. 1, #248A, p. 211).
This position is the basis for HegelÕs non-naturalist account of human
autonomy.
VI.
Read separately from the Logic and Philosophy of Nature, the early sections of the Philosophy of
Mind, in which Hegel explains how mind
emerges from nature, could easily be taken to express naturalism ˆ la
Novalis. Hegel claims that in organisms,
the nature of each part (or ÒmemberÓ) is completely shaped by its function for
the purposes of the whole organism, so that the organismÕs ÒformÓ constitutes
and completely pervades its parts (Hegel, 1971, #381A, p. 10). Consequently,
the form is sentient, for sentience (Empfindung) is the state of being a centre that encompasses or
overreaches, and is therefore in some sense present ÒwithinÓ, or returns into
itself from, each bodily part. Sentience marks the beginning of mind: Hegel
discusses sentience in the Philosophy of Nature as a characteristic of animals, but again in the Philosophy
of Mind as a characteristic of specifically
human animals, where it anticipates the higher levels of mind unique to humans.
Then in the early parts of the Philosophy of Mind, he traces the emergence of feeling (the initial
state of the sentient mind in which it is dispersed into its various
sensations), self-feeling (SelbstgefŸhl – a kind of
pre-reflective awareness of these sensations as oneÕs own), and consciousness (Bewu§tsein
– in which one begins to organise
these sensations under concepts, initially very thin concepts). By sensations
Hegel seems to understand bodily states or events insofar as the organismÕs
form is ÒwithinÓ them. However exactly we are to understand this, we can see
generally how HegelÕs account of mind could appear to build on the teleological
naturalism of Novalis. So construed, Hegel would be saying that nature pursues
self-integration and achieves it to the highest level in organisms, whereupon
that integration assumes the new form of mind, which in turn strives to
integrate itself further (by judging sensations under concepts, etc.), this
pursuit of integration being an extension of natureÕs pursuit of integration.
However, Hegel
stresses that Òmind É differentiates itself
from natureÓ (Hegel, 1971, #381A, p. 11), and that the specific mode of mindÕs
emergence from nature is a progressive liberation from nature rather than a
realisation of nature to a higher level:
The
illusory appearance that mind is mediated by something other [i.e. nature] is
sublated by mind itself, since this has É the sovereign ingratitude of
sublating that by which it appears to be mediated, É and in this way making
itself completely self-subsistent. (Hegel, 1971, #381A, p. 14)
The culmination of this process
within individuals is the emergence of human autonomy, the structure of which
Hegel describes in the introduction to his Philosophy of Right. Following Kant, he contrasts autonomy (or what he
calls Òobjective freedomÓ) to WillkŸr (Òsubjective freedomÓ), in which one simply selects which to follow of
oneÕs antecedently given desires. The
autonomous agent, in contrast, determines how to act solely from reason, and in
so doing s/he ÒovercomesÓ (Ÿberwindet), ÒbreaksÓ with (bricht)
or ÒremovesÓ (negiert) his or her
naturalness (Hegel, 1991b, pp. 377, 333, 319). Hegel regards this activity of
determining norms from reason as the highest level of an activity of organising
and shaping its own content which the mind began to undertake by feeling its
sensations to be its own and then by judging them under concepts. Crucially,
this organising activity is said not to be natural – it is not, as
Novalis held, the continuation of natureÕs self-integrating activity –
but, on the contrary, non-natural.
How is this so?
HegelÕs answer
relies on his view that nature is the self-externalised idea. As we saw, the
idea increasingly returns to itself within nature in the sense that it
increasingly re-assumes the form of form,
of centres of non-material rational activity which organise matter without
being material themselves. The more the idea resumes non-material form, the
less the idea is natural (or, what is equivalent, the less the idea is self-externalised).
Once the idea enters the form of organic form, in which it completely organises
matter, we reach the threshold where nature ceases and mind begins. However,
since the sensations that mind is initially to organise are states of the relevant body, why does Hegel not think
that mind is still organising matter and so is still natural – a form in
which the idea remains entangled with the self-external, material, bodily forms
of itself that it is organising? Hegel admits that the mind initially remains
natural: it is the ÒtruthÓ (the product) of nature and as such exists as what
he calls the Ònatural soulÓ (Hegel, 1971, #388, p. 29; #390, p. 34). But in
organising its sensations, the mind generates new structures – concepts,
judgements, principles of action – which, as organising principles, are
non-material, so that insofar as it is engaged in constructing and
systematising these principles, the mind is no longer natural.[16]
When the mind constructs practical principles for itself from reason, then, the
mind is acting non-naturally; so that the idea, in these higher forms of mind,
has fully returned to itself from its entanglement in matter. Of course, this
does not mean that an autonomous, rational person is qua autonomous disembodied; any such person retains a
body as that self-externalised form out of which the idea continually returns
to itself, but in thus returning to itself the idea reorganises itself along
non-natural, self-given lines. In HegelÕs own terms, then, his account of mind
is non-naturalist, because on this account the mind in its higher-level
functions is not natural. ÒMind that is in and for itself is not the mere
result of nature, but is in truth its own result; it brings itself forthÓ (Hegel, 1971, #381A, p. 14; my
emphasis). This non-naturalist account of mind rests on a broader ontology that
is non-naturalist because it grounds nature in the idea, a system of rational
structures that precedes the natural world.
However, this
anti-naturalist reading of Hegel could be challenged, notably by McDowell
(1994), from whose perspective Hegel situates human desires within Òsecond
natureÓ, always already enculturated and morally educated so that no Kantian
account of autonomy is required. While Hegel does indeed employ the concept of
Òsecond natureÓ (Hegel, 1991c, #151, p. 195), for him what permits our desires
and sensations to become culturally educated is the fact that they are in
themselves ÒconceptualÓ in the sense that I have examined: they are form-matter
hybrids. But for Hegel this is a feature of our desires and sensations prior to
any enculturation, because nature itself
(nature in the sense of Òfirst natureÓ) already has a conceptual side. By
taking this view Hegel avoids making mature human perception qualitatively
different from animal perception as McDowell seems pushed to do by his concept
of Òsecond natureÓ. But Hegel avoids this only by adopting his anti-naturalist
view that nature is grounded in the idea.
Still, part of
McDowellÕs objection remains: if our desires and sensations are conceptual and
educable by reason, then why should Hegel need a Kantian view of autonomy? The
answer is that for Hegel our desires and sensations are imperfectly rational,
because in them the idea remains Òoutside itselfÓ, entangled with matter. It is
because they are only imperfectly rational that our desires and sensations need
to be educated in light of the perfect rationality of the idea that has
Òreturned to itselfÓ. That is, our desires and sensations must be educated and
cultivated to accord with what we rationally determine to be normative. A
Kantian view of autonomy is thus built into HegelÕs conception of the ideaÕs
self-externalisation within, and self-restoration from, nature.
On my view, then,
Hegel sees as rational human self-determination as prefigured by the prior form
of rational self-organisation exercised by nature, whereby nature gives itself
its structure from reason in virtue of being the (self-external) idea. NatureÕs
rational self-organisation makes possible human autonomy because as nature
structures itself rationally, the idea progressively re-emerges within nature
so that it can then assume the higher form of mind. Once arisen, the mind
progressively breaks with nature, a progression that culminates in autonomous
self-determination. But what makes these breaks possible is the structure of
nature itself as self-cancelling, as the sphere in which the idea gradually
overcomes its self-externalisation as matter.
Hegel resolves the
conflicts in Romantic metaphysics, retaining KantÕs view that human autonomy
involves a break with desire and with nature, while yet explaining how the
human capacity to make this break emerges from nature. But HegelÕs resolution
comes at the cost of a non-naturalist metaphysics and philosophy of mind. We might
therefore think that the more worthwhile approach to nature and mind is the
naturalist approach of Novalis, and that he should simply have abandoned his
residual Kantian commitment to the opposition between reason and desire. He
could then have said that our desires already, naturally, exhibit a level of
rationality and so can be educated and cultivated – educated in
accordance with a rationality that remains natural itself, constituting a
higher-level realisation of natureÕs rationality. However, this form of
naturalism relies on the idea that nature has a telos to become systematically integrated and in that sense
rational. But while this view of nature counted as naturalist in relation to
the sciences of NovalisÕs own time, which tended to support that view, it is
less clear that NovalisÕs view can count as naturalist for us today. At first
glance at least, little in contemporary science (with partial exceptions, such
as Gaia theory) seems to bear out NovalisÕs view that nature is a
systematically self-organising whole. It remains a matter for further
investigation, then, whether anything like NovalisÕs approach to nature and
mind can be retained against the background of contemporary scientific accounts
of nature.
References
Beiser, Frederick C. (2002): German
Idealism: The Struggle against Subjectivism, 1781-1801, Cambridge.
Beiser, Frederick C. (2005): Hegel, Abingdon.
Berlin, Isaiah (1999): The Roots
of Romanticism, Princeton.
Gardner, Sebastian (2007): ÒThe
Limits of Naturalism and the Metaphysics of German Idealism,Ó in: German
Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives, ed.
Hammer, Espen, London, pp. 38-44.
Frank, Manfred (1997): Unendliche
AnnŠherung: Die AnfŠnge der philosophischen FrŸhromantik, Frankfurt.
Halper, Edward (1998): ÒThe Logic
of HegelÕs Philosophy of Nature: Nature,
Space and Time,Ó in Hegel and the Philosophy of Nature, ed. Houlgate, Stephen, Albany.
Hegel Philosophy of Nature
Hegel, G. W. F. (1970): Philosophy
of Nature, 3 vols., trans. Petry, M. J.,
Oxford.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1971): Philosophy
of Mind, trans. Wallace, William and A. V.
Miller, Oxford.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1972): Werke, ed. Moldenhauer, Eva and Karl Markus Michel,
Frankfurt.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1975): Aesthetics:
Lectures on Fine Art, trans. Knox, T. M.,
Oxford.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1991a): The
Encyclopaedia Logic, trans. Geraets, T. F.,
W. A. Suchting and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1991b): The
Philosophy of History, trans. Sibree, J.
Buffalo, NY.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1991c): Elements
of the Philosophy of Right, trans. Nisbet,
H. B., Cambridge.
Houlgate, Stephen (2007): ÒHegel
and Brandom on Norms, Concepts and Logical Categories,Ó in: German Idealism:
Contemporary Perspectives, ed. Hammer,
Espen, London, pp. 137-152.
Kant, Immanuel (1987): Critique
of Judgement, trans. Pluhar, Werner S.,
Indianapolis
Kemp Smith, Norman (1920): ÒThe
Present Situation in Philosophy,Ó in: The Philosophical Review, 29(1), pp. 1-26.
Maker, William (1998): ÒThe Very
Idea of Nature, or Why Hegel Is Not an Idealist,Ó in Hegel and the Philosophy
of Nature, ed. Houlgate, Stephen, Albany.
McDowell, John (1994): Mind and
World, Cambridge, Mass.
Novalis (1975): Schriften, ed. Samuel, Richard, Stuttgart.
Novalis (1997): Philosophical
Writings, ed. Stoljar, Margaret Mahony,
Albany.
Novalis (2003): Fichte Studies, ed. Kneller, Jane, Cambridge.
Novalis (2007): Notes for a
Romantic Encyclopedia: Das Allgemeine Brouillon, trans. and ed. Wood, David W., Albany.
Pinkard, Terry (2002): German
Philosophy 1760-1860: The Legacy of Idealism,
Cambridge.
Pippin, Robert (1999): ÒNaturalness
and Mindedness: HegelÕs Compatibilism,Ó in: Journal of European Philosophy, 7(2), pp. 194-212.
Pippin, Robert (2005): The
Persistence of Subjectivity: On the Kantian Aftermath, Cambridge.
Richards, Robert J. (2002): The
Romantic Conception of Life: Science and Philosophy in the Age of Goethe, Chicago.
Schlegel, Friedrich (1991): Philosophical
Fragments, trans. Firchow, Peter,
Minneapolis.
Stone, Alison (2004): Petrified
Intelligence: Nature in HegelÕs Philosophy,
Albany.
Stone, Alison (2005): ÒÔFriedrich
Schlegel, Romanticism, and the Re-enchantment of NatureÓ, in: Inquiry 48(1), pp. 3-25.
[1] I believe that the same is also true of Friedrich Schlegel, who comes to see human poetic creativity (which he regards as autonomous) as an outgrowth of the creativity of nature; see Stone 2005.
[2] I speak of Ônon-Õ rather than Ôanti-naturalismÕ here because Pinkard and Pippin construe Hegel as a Ônon-metaphysicalÕ thinker whose claims are consistent with the naturalist ontological thesis that all existents obey laws of nature (Pippin, 1999; 2005). On this reading, for Hegel autonomy requires not that agents have any metaphysical power for uncaused self-determination but merely the capacity to Ôtake their lives in a certain wayÕ (Pinkard, 2002, p. 287) and so to be beholden solely to those reasons or values that they take to be authoritative. These reasons and values stand in the logical space of how agents ought to (rather than do in fact) think and act – a Ôspace of reasonsÕ that is logically (rather than metaphysically) irreducible to the Ôspace of natural lawÕ.
[3] John McDowell would agree, but would think that this complication calls for a revised definition of naturalism. For him, Hegel does not limit ÒnatureÓ to the physical nature of the empirical sciences but also includes within ÒnatureÓ our Òsecond natureÓ, our culturally educated desires, sensations and moral dispositions, which are natural because enculturation is Òa normal part of what it is for a human being to come to maturityÓ (McDowell, 1994, p. 84). Hegel is, on this view, a kind of naturalist, taking the ÒnatureÓ in naturalism to comprise physical and ÒsecondÓ nature. So for McDowell, Hegel has no need to understand autonomy as involving abstraction from desire, because he already treats desires as rational. I interpret Hegel differently; see section VI.
[4] Although for the Romantics, the only possible system is a system-in-progress (see Schlegel, 1991).
[5] From PippinÕs perspective Idealist and Romantic accounts of nature are uninteresting because they explain the natural origins of a capacity that, once arisen, is non-natural (which inaugurates the non-natural space of reasons). Pinkard (2002) gives Naturphilosophie slightly more shrift; he argues that it reconstructs the concept of nature that is needed to make science intelligible: namely, the concept of nature as non-normative in contrast to the normative space of reasons, this contrast (allegedly) being needed to make science intelligible as a norm-governed practice. However, the German Romantics and Idealists reject these sharp contrasts between the rational and the natural, the normative and the natural. For them nature already exercises rationality in organising itself, and nature follows norms in so doing. Pippin would reject such views of nature as misguided metaphysics. But before we can assess whether these views are misguided, we must acknowledge that the Romantics and Idealists did engage in this kind of metaphysical theorising about nature, and must examine the content of their metaphysical theories.
[6] Translations from Novalis and Hegel have sometimes been amended in light of, respectively, Novalis (1975) and Hegel (1972).
[7] For Novalis, then, a ÔthingÕ is an individual entity that is as it is because it is causally conditioned to be so by other such entities, and which differs from other such entities in its properties such that it falls under different concepts from those others.
[8] Beiser, 2005, pp. 95-96, clearly explains the distinction between composite and synthetic wholes.
[9] Thus, Isaiah Berlin (1999) is not wholly wrong to attribute a belief in irrational, arbitrary will to the Romantics; he errs in seeing this belief as a central rather than a minor element in Romanticism.
[10] Of course this is one of HegelÕs criticisms of Romanticism, made apropos of the ÔRomantic ironyÕ of Schlegel; see Hegel, 1975, pp. 64-65.
[11] Not surprisingly, therefore, Novalis sometimes equates the absolute with God – not SpinozaÕs pantheist God, but a personal God who exercises volition (Novalis, 2003, #151, p. 55).
[12] So Beiser shows (2002, 2005). As far as I know Hegel aimed to systematise not NovalisÕs ideas specifically but the general Romantic view of the absolute, the tensions in which are played out not only in NovalisÕs work but also in that of other Romantics, such as Schlegel – see Stone 2005. In this task Hegel built on Schelling, who he believed had not succeeded in completely systematising the Romantic view.
[13] Hegel himself often speaks of ÔtensionsÕ (Spannungen) in natural kinds; see Stone, 2004, p. 183.
[14] For more on how the idea self-externalises to produce nature, see Maker (1998), Halper (1998).
[15] For example, Hegel claims that because space is self-contradictory, the idea necessarily enters into the improved form of time (Hegel, 1970, vol. 1, #257A, p. 229).
[16] Ô[I]t is man who first raises himself above the singleness of sensation to the universality of thought É in a word, it is only man who is thinking mind and by this, and by this alone, is essentially distinguished from natureÕ (Hegel, 1971, #381A, p. 14). For Hegel there is no mystery about how the mind can produce non-material structures: the mind is the idea as rational constructive activity. Any mystery here (of which Hegel hopes there is none) already applies to the logical idea.